These days Martin Heidegger is mostly talked about for being a Nazi. Most of the justification for dismissing his work stems from the assumption that his philosophical views led him to a position of loyal Nazism, when in fact they could have had very little to do with it. Rather than argue the historical points of the man's involvement, I think it useful to pursue the actual ethical ramifications of the man's work. In this way I hope to both encourage further Heidegger scholarship without fear of the stigma involved as well as hopefully advancing (or destructing) the field of ethics in the same way as with metaphysics. Because of the way he worded his arguments, many of Heidegger's most value-neutral ideas have been interpreted as ethical macguffins. Foremost among these is the idea of authenticity, the mode of being of Da-sein (Heidegger's term for one's self, which for now the reader not versed in Heidegger can take to mean his or her self in particular) in which Da-sein is attuned so thoroughly toward its death that it can "'choose' itself in its being, it can win itself, it can lose itself, or it can never and only 'apparently' win itself. It can only have lost itself and it can only have not yet gained itself because it is essentially possible as authentic, that is, it belongs to itself." [BT 42-43] This can begin to sound like a pursuit, since words like "authentic", "belongs", "itself", "lose", and "win" carry the burdens of good and bad sentiment. The fact is that Heidegger explicitly stated that authenticity was in no way "better" or "higher" than inauthenticity. The words are to be understood in a much more literal sense, with any notions about the value of purity thrown aside as arbitrary and irrelevant. The terms simply describe motivations, the lines of thought Da-sein follows in making decisions. Authenticity and inauthenticity are both essential features of Da-sein. "[T]he inauthenticity of Da-sein does not signify a 'lesser' being or a 'lower' degree of being. Rather, inauthenticity can determine Da-sein even in its fullest concretion, when it is busy, excited, interested, and capable of pleasure." [BT 43] In fact, getting beyond one's existing understanding of the terms Heidegger uses is one of the most important steps to understanding what he wrote. This leaves the question, then, of what part of Heidegger's philosophy makes an ethical claim, or if ethics is even possible in such a valueless system. It is true, of course, that the aim of his project is itself a value claim. Heidegger's project is to get to the meaning of being, and the value claim is that this is a worthy pursuit. It is even clear from his language that he saw it as necessary to properly engage in philosophy. These are certainly value claims, but he is careful to never claim that having these understandings can dictate how a person should think or act. This is because, from a perspective of fundamental ontology, dictation can not be the shape of ethics. The reasons for this will reveal themselves as we investigate how Heidegger's understanding of truth differs from that of what he calls metaphysics*, the western metaphysical tradition. *"In its \textit{scholastic} mold, Greek ontology makes the essential transition...into the 'metaphysics' and transcendental philosophy of the modern period" [BT 22]. The conception of truth around which metaphysics operates is that of logos. This is the idea of direct correspondence with a catalogue of fact, that one can compare a claim to a reference point of knowledge and deduce its correctness. That a thing is either true or false is a guiding presupposition of this conception. Heidegger instead argued that, before Plato and Aristotle cemented this idea of truth, another explanation was possible. For this he used another Greek word for truth, aletheia, which he translated as "unconcealment". Instead of a well-defined, whole, and rarefied expression of absolute fact, truth is a "pulling back of the curtain", gaining a perspective on something while at the same time covering part of it over [Undelivered Lecture (XII) Section 4, p.179-181]. This is not a deficient form of truth, but rather a representation of how anything like truth can exist in a phenomenological methodology. When one's access to a "thing itself" is one's relationship with it, truth is something revealed in that relationship. The ramifications of this approach for ontology are well explored and not the focus of this paper. Instead we shall look to its influence on the field of ethics. Namely, that it is not the job of ethics to proscribe action according to an objective truth, but that ethics must instead guide action according to the relationships beings have with each other. We will explore these relationships in depth later, but not before we look at the kind of ethics that results from the conception of truth as logos. The most thorough example of western metaphysical ethics comes from Kant. The idea of treating people as something other than a means to an end, the point that good actions are good not because of the action but the intent behind them, and the necessity of behaving according to a rule that should be applicable to anyone are central notions in Kant's ethics. These ideas are variously justified or annihilated by Heidegger's fundamental ontology of Da-sein, as we shall see. Even though his project was to get to the meaning of being---a far more elaborate project than justifying an ethical system---Heidegger's demonstration of Da-sein and being-in or -with is groundbreaking for discussion of "human" motivation and will. Because we are taking this route there are some features common to ethical systems that we will be throwing away or replacing: 1: There is no rule. Just as truth and existence have nothing to do with correspondence to an outside feature, proper behavior can no longer have anything to do with propriety or adherence to an absolute. If this sounds foolish and weak it's important to stress that at no point does Heidegger's philosophy support purely "subjective" standpoints. The discussion will no longer be one of rationality and logic, but instead one of being-with, circumspection, authenticity, and resoluteness. 2: There is no self. Authenticity is a mode of being, not an absolute state. It is impossible to be without being in the world, and the sealing of this dichotomy (self and world) means we can no longer speak in rarefied terms about what a person is. This does not mean we're operating in some kind of transcendent overmind! If Heidegger's approach seems sometimes dangerously close to solipsistic it is only because he so brazenly confronts the issue. Few philosophers enjoy considering it for long, but the always-mine-ness of Da-sein leaves no choice. The result is that solipsism is always there, made irrelevant by the new approach phenomenology affords and the new conception of the self as being in a world. There will be few thought experiments. 3: There is free will. What form this takes is up for discussion, but as we are starting from the position of that being that questions and makes decisions we are in a great sense taking free will as a given. This is not a presupposition per se, but a consequence of the fact that our investigation begins from experience rather than objectively measurable data. Whether this is an acceptable starting point is a matter of debate beyond the scope of this paper. If we are to continue at all we must address one of Heidegger's most fundamental concepts: that of Da-sein. For the purpose of simplicity the reader can always take Da-sein to refer to his or her self, but the reasons for and consequences of this term must be understood if any progress is to be made. Most attempts at defining humanity are most dangerously flawed. This is mostly because they are simultaneously completely founded on an assumption and blatantly tautological. The assumption is that there must be some characteristic of humanity that is unique among all beings, however they may be defined, and the tautology is that, whatever distinction one uses as justification for this assumption, it can only ever function within an argument as a stand-in for "humanity". Heidegger's approach was to abandon all presupposition of which beings ought to interest his investigation and instead address the particular behavior that was of interest to his project: being interested in one's own being. In asking and thinking about its being, this being exists both ontically, in that it exists in the world, and ontologically, in that world exists for and with it, in that it questions its own existence. No assumption is made about whether all humans have this kind of being, just as no assumption is made about whether any other "species" of life has it. In exploring its relationship with its world, however, we find that neither issue is of any relevance at all. What \textit{is} relevant, and what is fundamentally different from any approach before, is that this being cannot be separated from its world. The entire stage of modern epistemology, where the subject is cut off from a world of objects and has experiences based on sense data, has been removed from the picture. In its place we have this being, which is always in a there. It is therefore inappropriate to think of it in rarefied terms, and Heidegger dubbed it Da-sein (being-there). The ramifications of this approach will reveal their relevance as our departure from Kant unfolds. For Kant the world was a product of the subject, a rationally inferred construction of sense data into a coherent system. This was groundbreaking in the way it evaded the problems of truth as correspondence, but it also dug philosophy even deeper into the problems of Cartesian dualism and the res cogitans, since the world was still founded upon something that the self has no way of interacting with directly, and the modern dichotomy between determinism and skepticism remained as strong as ever. Kant's reliance on logic and rational processes was the seed of his ethics, too, and his definition of humanity as the capacity for reason and deductive thought was instrumental in his adoption of logic as the horizon for ethics. By emphasizing the need for internal consistency, Kant was able to require various behaviors in order to preserve a system wherein the self could continue to behave rationally. As a result, any rational being must be treated as the goal of ethics. Hence, people must be treated as ends in themselves rather than as means to ends. This ideal arose partly out of Kant's preconception of what a proper ethical system should look like ("The sole aim of the present Groundwork is to seek out and establish \textit{the supreme principle of morality}.")[GMM 60] and partly out of reverence for logical justification (arbitrariness)[GMM 69, Footnote 2]. Kant's project is a deductive proof of why a deductive system must preserve and revere beings with the capacity for deductive reasoning, but this approach values people only insofar as they behave rationally. In Kant's words, "Rational beings,...are called \textit{persons} because their nature already marks them out as ends in themselves..." [GMM 96]. People are people because their rationality is to be preserved in order to have a rational universe. How can we establish this without all these presuppositions? What are other people for Da-sein? When Heidegger explains how Da-sein exists with other beings in the world, a distinction is made between how Da-sein interacts with useful things, tools, and how Da-sein interacts with other people. The former is understood in terms of in-order-to and what-for, and is taken as a matter of "care", whereas in the latter case Da-sein recognizes others as being like itself and treats them with "concern", which we will explore later in more detail. While these other beings are understood in how they are like Da-sein, they can not accurately be called "Da-sein". To Da-sein, they are those being with whom one is in the world, and they are called "Mitda-sein" ("being-there-with") This interaction, and the concept of Mitda-sein, are significant aspects of any attempt at Heideggerian ethics. There is much ethical territory that Heidegger did not cover. To fill these gaps we will attempt to approach the fundamental aspect of ethics in the same way Heidegger did the fundamental question of being. The parallels are extensive, most significantly in how both ethics and being are concepts most frequently "explained" via assumption and then handled as rational structures. Our approach will be Heidegger's: to discover what understanding of ethical behavior Da-sein always already has but cannot express. As with being, we will be able to highlight this understanding throughout metaphysics while detailing how it came to be misrepresented. In a foundational work of western metaphysical ethics, Plato's \textit{Republic}, the pivotal question was asked: do we behave justly for its own sake or for the worldly rewards? Glaucon supposed that, were one able to turn invisible and act without fear of consequences, one would rape and/or pillage whatever one could [Republic II 359-360]. Plato's response was an elaborate analogy between the justice of an individual and the justice of a city, a thought experiment culminating in his assertion that just behavior leads necessarily to a healthy soul, and is therefore necessary for happiness [Republic IV 444-445]. This split omitted an important possibility: that relationships with people are valuable in their own right. This aspect of ethics would not be thoroughly entered into the equation until Kant, and by then the damage caused by dualistic metaphysics was too extensive to come to any worthwhile conclusions with the revelation, let alone approach it in a pre-Platonic fashion. One must take care now not to start attaching a value to "relationships with people". I bring it up not to chase after it as the seed of a logically determined and arbitrary system, but to demonstrate that it is possible for the aforementioned worldly rewards to be the kindness of others, or for it to feel good to make another happy. To suddenly treat kindness as a selfish behavior may seem cynical, but we are not necessarily treating this relation as one between a subject and object. Kant was trying to get away from this, but his system did not allow for any other kind of relation. Heidegger offers us the chance to look at benevolent behavior as an act of connection and familiarity. Kant wanted people to be considered ends in themselves, but Heidegger's contribution is to remove them from the system of means and ends entirely. Mitda-sein are accomplices, other beings of the same kind as Da-sein. In them Da-sein can see its own possibilities. The field of ethics seems largely interested in expressing formally something Da-sein feels it understands. Liberated from the need to express it formally, we are now free to examine this understanding that Da-sein always already has. [B&T 124 is key here, and all of sections 26 & 27] In being-with Mitda-sein, Da-sein understands the need to be-excellent-with Mitda-sein. The formal ethics of Kant and co. are attempts to live according to certain rules of action, but as you can see there is nothing in being-excellent which determines any particular right or wrong action. The emphasis here is on the interests of Da-sein and Mitda-sein, on what they want or need and what they are willing to do for one another. It is beneficial at this point to elaborate on the role of Mitda-sein in the constitution of Da-sein, since it is such a radical departure from the solipsistic foundation of Descartes. For Heidegger the other is not understood as something distinct from the self, alien and separate, but rather as "...those from whom one mostly does NOT distinguish oneself, those among whom one is, too." [BT 118] In this way Da-sein understands its being-in-the-world as a being-with others. "The innerwordly being-in-itself of others is Mitda-sein." [BT 118] Over time this relation can lose its distinctiveness. As Da-sein compares itself to Mitda-sein, it takes on a pressure to equalize its difference from others. As this occurs, the specific "who" of Mitda-sein dissolves into a "they", into das Man (note that this "they" is in actuality a "we"). This relationship promotes "averageness", an equilibrium which discourages anything but aquiescence to what is familiar and accepted. This is variously referred to as degenerate, levelled down, and public [BT 126-127]. Here we encounter some of Heidegger's most value-tinted language, and it begins to look as though the inquiry has found its hobgoblin. But even authentic Da-sein does not simply remove itself from publicness. "\textit{Authentic being one's self} is not...a state detached from the they, \textit{but is an existentiell modification of the they as an essential existential}." [BT 130] All we have here is an analysis of the different ways Da-sein understands Mitda-sein, and how those affect Da-sein's understanding of its world. There is no reason to conclude that any of this is grounds for a systematic ethics. It does, however, provide us with the horizon for a new approach. Da-sein's understanding of the other in terms of its sameness contributes both to Da-sein's understanding of itself and levelling down of itself. This is the span of human relationships in which something like ethics becomes possible. In being-excellent, Da-sein behaves ethically in the most primordial sense of the term. Whatever the particulars, Da-sein is behaving conducively to the good of its being-with-others. It's dangerous to think of this as behavior that promotes entanglement, or that gives up the potential for authenticity. Being-excellent is not a sacrifice of one's own interests or a plunge headlong into entanglement in das Man. Being-excellent is Da-sein's recognition that when it is in a world with others, just as it is thrown together with Mitda-sein its interests, too, are thrown together with those of Mitda-sein. As you can see, this does not fall anywhere between resoluteness and entanglement. Excellence is not an aspect of Da-sein, but a mode of concern. As Heidegger points out for us, there are two possible extremes of concern. The first is to leap in for Mitda-sein and take its "care" away from it, to use or manipulate it in ways seen or unseen [BT 122]. This is Heidegger's version of treating people as means to ends. The second is to leap ahead of Mitda-sein, to give his care back to him. This is concern about authentic care, about Mitda-sein's existence, and not about the things it takes care of [BT 122]. This is Heidegger's version of treating people as ends in themselves. Our goal lies not between these extremes, but across them. In having concern for Mitda-sein, Da-sein is constantly treating it in all of these ways and more. Being-excellent-with Mitada-sein is not a matter of maximizing behavior of a particular kind, but of establishing alliance. Being-excellent is a looking-out-for, it is Da-sein carrying Mitda-sein along with it. In having allies, Da-sein can be authentically appreciating their influences or inauthentically falling prey along with them. A notion in Heidegger that can not be left uninvestigated in any attempt to make his work ethical is that of conscience. For Heidegger, conscience is not what calls Da-sein to ethical behavior or "doing what's right", but instead it is quite specifically calling Da-sein back to itself, out of entanglement and back to authenticity. Even guilt, for Heidegger, is ontological. Guilt is the lack, the not-yet, of Da-sein's being. Da-sein's progression toward its end is "put off" by entanglement, its awareness of the inevitability of death is "tranquillized" by das Man. As constantly communicating, das Man covers over Da-sein with talk. Conscience calls Da-sein back to its possibility of authenticity through reticence, allowing (but not forcing) Da-sein to come forth from das Man [BT 271-274]. In understanding this call, in choosing itself and becoming free for the call, Da-sein is aware of the putting off of its end and wants to have a conscience, wants to be called back to its ownmost potentiality of being [BT 287-288]. The traditional idea that conscience is the call back to just behavior is a misunderstanding of where the call comes from. The call does not come from outside of Da-sein. The caller is not defined by anything worldly, but is uncanny, thrown being-in-the-world, is Da-sein's being-in-the-world itself. Not alien to Da-sein, the caller is alien to the average, everyday self of das Man [BT 276-278]. "This being guilty first gives the ontological condition for the fact that Da-sein can become guilty while factically existing. This essential being guilty is, equiprimordially, the existential condition of the possibility of the 'morally' good and evil, that is, for morality in general and its possible factical forms." [BT 286] Facticity is the way a being exists in the world, distinguished from factuality in that it does not exist as objectively present but as in the world, bound up in its destiny with the other beings there encountered [BT 56]. This quote refers to morality, addressing the derivative form of conscience as a call back to just behavior. The "morality" of the understood call is Da-sein being responsible, letting "its ownmost self \textit{take action in itself} in terms of its chosen potentiality-of-being" [BT 288]. Let us take care not to forget that the ownmost self of Da-sein is not the ego cogito, but a being-in-the-world that understands its being as a being-with-others. Even authentic being-a-self is a modification of the they [BT 267]. What form does "self-love" take when the self is thus defined? It does not look at all like Glaucon's supposition that if one could keep others ignorant of our wrongdoings one would steal and rape. Being-excellent is the primordial ethics which the so-called "vulgar understanding of being [which] understands 'being' as objective presence" [BT 389], the Cartesian concept of the self as an isolated spirit, can only understand as self-love in Glaucon's sense. The action taken as Da-sein, in being-guilty, chooses its potentiality-of-being, being-excellent is a love of the relationship Da-sein has with Mitda-sein, is the ethical imperative of concern. In the wake of Heidegger's ontological work, we can start to outline the shape ethics takes for Da-sein. Just as with spatiality and temporality, the Western tradition of metaphysics has covered over the possibility of ethics by assuming that behaviors must be morally calculable as independent "universal" principles. An ontologically-grounded approach to ethics does not designate correct factical action, but instead lays bare the role and meaning of Mitda-sein. In being-excellent-with Mitda-sein, Da-sein already understands being-excellent as concern, as the role of its being-with-others in its understanding of the call of conscience. The problem of ethics has never been defining justice or goodness. These are degenerate forms of excellence, which is always already understood. The problem of ethics is recognizing what beings Da-sein understands as Mitda-sein. A vegetarian may recognize an animal in the mode of being-with where a carnivore does not, or where the carnivore understands its being-with the animal from a position of gratefulness to it for its sustenance. One person believes a barely-formed fetus to be Mitda-sein, and will thus react to an abortion in a manner very different from one who merely sees a thing at hand and objectively present. This approach is, perhaps, of little use in answering these problems. This is because the problem is already answered for Da-sein. Instead of debating what action is right, we can only try to convince each other of what beings deserve to be treated excellently. Only on this basis can we begin to approach our most common ethical questions, and even then they can never be solved. Instead of codifying rules of behavior, by being-excellent Da-sein pulls back the curtain on the problem and approaches it based on its relationship to it.